The main problem with this is simply that it's not clear what it means for a distribution to be uniform in this case. We could generalize uniformity to be relative, i.e., a probability measure μ is uniform relative to measure ν iff μ = cν for some constant c. Our standard sense of uniformity would be relative to the Lebesgue measure (and indeed that's exactly what we're doing when we think of uniform probability as proportional to interval length), but of course the Cantor set has Lebesgue measure zero, so no probability measure over the Cantor set is going to be compatible with it in this sense.Dark Lord of the Bith wrote:I mean a random variable x with a uniform probability distribution P(x) where x is in the Cantor set (C). So given a random number from C, what's the probability that x is in some uncountable subset U of C?
Let's try it. Build the Cantor set C in the standard manner: let C_0 = [0,1] and C_{n+1} = {x/3,2/3+x/3: x in C_n}, thus removing the middle-third of each subinterval, and C be the intersection of all C_n. Let f:[0,1]→C be defined by Sum[ a_n/2^n ] ↦ Sum[ 2a_n/3^n ], where each a_n is in {0,1} and n>0. Finally, for a random variable X with uniform distribution over [0,1], let Y = f(X). Then Y takes values only in the Cantor set and has the additional property that for a fixed n, if takes any subinterval contained in any particular Cantor iterate C_n, the probability that Y is in that subinterval is directly proportional to its length.Dark Lord of the Bith wrote:As an example, let U be [0, .5] intersected with C (in other words, the first half of the Cantor set). Then it would naively seem that the chance of x being in U is 1/2, but I'm not sure how to show it.
This is something close to the sense you're using, and I suppose that it is reasonable to call uniform. The probability measure itself would be the μ(f^{-1}), where μ is the Lebesgue measure.
You can't paint it only if you're required to have a uniform thickness of your coat of paint or otherwise have some unfortunate lower bound conditions on it.madd0ct0r wrote:In other words, you cannot paint it - it has an infinite area and so you'd be there forever and never have enough paint.
Indeed. That's why in analysis, 'almost everywhere' means 'everywhere but on a set of measure zero'. It's the exact same thing with probability, just with the additional condition that the measure is a probability measure.Winston Blake wrote:1 doesn't mean 'certain to happen' and 0 doesn't mean 'certain not to happen'. They're infinitesimally close to being certain, so they're called 'almost certain'.