Iosef Cross wrote:That's because it is a thinking shortcut: If somebody suggests some kind of intervention, it has to be analyzed deeply. Since as a rule of thumb intervention tends to be not good. It has a very good rationale behind it.
But that's retarded. First of all because of a HUGE lack of evidence supporting this rule of thumb, and second of all because it is almost never a good idea to use a rule of thumb to analyze a situation before stopping to consider whether the rule of thumb applies.
If you start by assuming "government bad!" before looking around to see whether there are externality problems that would make government
good in this situation, you're going to make a lot of foolish mistakes and ignore a lot of practical problems.
Stas Bush wrote:Capitalist anarchy is not viable.
Worse than that, it's a contradiction in terms. Capital in an anarchy falls into the hands of whoever has the most firepower, and that qualification does
not make them well-placed to use their capital in ways that "capitalist" societies normally do.
Now, capitalist minarchy is at least not an oxymoron, even if it isn't a good form of government. Because there you have a powerful organization enforcing property and contract law.
Iosef Cross wrote:Since when did that become a "rule of thumb"? Did someone do the analysis of Y million government interventions in all the nations of the world and their outcomes to determine the percentage of success, failure and/or mixed results? See, you're speaking like a libertarian. You trot out a statement, which is not corroborated by hard statistical data, and then say it's a "rule of thumb" and "good rationale".
The fact is that the market tends to generate tendencies were the factors if production tend to reflect underlying consumer preferences. This process tends to reach a state were the factors are allocated in a optimal way to satisfy the consumers.
All right; where's the corroborating evidence that such systems work
better as they are less regulated? You've made an argument from theoretical principles with an awful lot of "tends" in it; such arguments are often wrong. Supporting evidence is vital here.
"X tends to do Y" is not sufficient without math to show
how it does Y, to what degree, and under what circumstances. Because it may not always do Y, or it may not do nearly enough of Y to offset problem Z, or Y may not actually be worth doing on further examination.
You link to a study which shows a correlation between "economic freedom" and other positive indicators... but there are confounding variables at work here. Many "economically unfree" nations are also on the low end of the curve when it comes to matters of economic development, which is correlated with
both "unfree" policies
and indicators like life expectancy.
Moreover, the study fails to show a strong correlation. The "freest" countries are also the richest and best off, but there's no one to one correlation: the US is high on the "economic freedom index," but relatively low among developed countries in indicators like life expectancy, education, and such. Rates of economic growth are nearly the same among the first, second, and third quartiles of countries when those countries are organized by "economic freedom." Rates of foreign investment are nearly the same among the second, third, and fourth quartiles, with virtually
all developed nations lying in the first quartile.
So the question is: how much of this correlation between economic freedom and economic success is a coincidence?
What would be the incentive of the government to correct these inefficiencies? In a dictatorship the State doesn't have any incentive to correct economic inefficiencies, in this world the State only uses the population under it to satisfy it's own ends.
How is this not an incentive? I, for one, routinely feel an incentive to improve the quality of the tools I use.
When the market fails, that means that a benevolent and omniscient government could correct it. But the government is not omniscient nor benevolent.
Yes. However, this does not prove your desired conclusion: "Therefore, the government cannot correct the market."
To see why, consider: "If my car is parked in the wrong place, Superman could move it. But I am not Superman. Therefore, I cannot move my parked car."
This is obviously wrong. The fact that A matches a certain condition doesn't mean that B
doesn't. Compare this to the Masked Man fallacy: "I do not know who the masked man is. I know who my father is. Therefore, the masked man is not my father."
You haven't shown that governments
need to be perfectly benevolent and omniscient in order to correct market failures, so the fact that real governments aren't perfectly benevolent and omniscient is irrelevant to the question of whether they can correct market failures.