You keep using those words, libertarianism and statism. I do not think they mean what you think they mean. Seriously, there is nothing at all libertarian about holding that natural rights do not exist, that society is a construct for organizing power, and that complex bodies of law are necessary to keep society from breaking down. Nor would a statist claim that society shapes the social order that the state is upheld by, that rights exist in society because of conflict with/within the governing elite, and admit to the inevitability of slow evolution, or provide any kind of rationale at all for the state to not do something.Bakustra wrote:Purnell, are you going to justify why this negative formulation of lack of interference from government is better than a positive formulation of formal protection? I brought up lynching for a reason, as while the libertarian ideology from which you draw that tends to minimize this, rights can be infringed upon by ordinary citizens as well as the government. In other words, if you formulate rights solely as a negative of government interference, then a man getting lynched has not had his right to life infringed upon, and a man being beaten for being a Communist has not had his freedom of expression infringed upon either! This is ignoring rights that cannot be formulated with a negative- the right to contract is only meaningful if the contract's terms can be enforced upon both parties! If it's not necessary to formulate rights, only to avoid infringing upon them, then why do so many constitutions formally acknowledge them? Your argument fails descriptively on those grounds. I'm sure that you or your defenders will complain that this paragraph was just a bunch of stuff, but my point is that there are a number of flaws with your approach to rights.
Seeing as you've decided to mimic Simon by using utilitarianism, how can you use a subjective moral system to evaluate the consequences of what you claim to be an objective, universal system of social order, but disallow it for any other relationship to law? In other words, why allow utility in some cases and not in others? Simon misunderstood you as advocating utility in general with regards to the law, but you were not. Are you abandoning what you said earlier? That would seem to be the case, because you're admitting that what constitutes the social order varies from place to place. But you should acknowledge that, then, instead of saying that I'm strawmanning you with your own arguments!
Evaluating on socioeconomic status is tricky, especially since there are so many ways to measure it. Would you use median income, or mean income, or inflation, or a combination of economic factors? Because the US comes out very differently using different measures. But it also ignores intangibles. Consider the case that I brought up earlier. How do you evaluate whether Canada or the US is better at free speech between Canada's sharper restrictions on hate speech and the US's lack of the same? If we fully acknowledge the subjectivity of whether certain social orders are better or not, then it seems that your primary objection to the incorporation of morality, justice, et al into the law is fallen. Because if the question is between whether the social order would be better with this level of protection or that for the freedom of the press, then justice is as valid as socioeconomic status for argumentation and your beliefs falter. But if you don't want to surrender this, explain how an objective approach to the highest social order can be constructed, given subtle differences between various developed nations.
As for your example, lynchings and beatings of people are a violation of both public peace and the social order; they were always illegal as such. The lack of enforcement was unfortunate, but an example of how particular moral codes can subvert the functioning of the law. Laws, societies, governments, states being imperfect? News at Eleven. My argument was never that ideals exist in real life but that the law must necessarily uphold public order to see to the functioning of society. The importance of contract law to social functioning should also be blatantly obvious, and hence with it the state's affirmative role in enforcing it. Of course it is also conceivable to imagine a society without any "right" to a contract, probably in some tribal setting where dealings with outsiders are not on the same level as anyone within the group. But for anything more complex than that, I expect it began with two merchants making a solemn oath to the Gods and when one did not deliver, the other appealed to the magistrates to punish the oath-breaker. A good deal of social evolution later and the contract in a modern form was born.
In any case I do not need to justify the existence of every single right, since all of those rights are culturally and socially determined. Indeed as I have consistently maintained rights are completely meaningless outside of a society, and are only possible to speak of within the order and peace established by such. There are as many variations of what constitutes a right as there are societies, since rights are essentially memes that have social consensus behind them. I have never held that there is some universal social order, which is something you pulled out of nowhere by misrepresenting how a theoretical model applies to the real world. There are certainly aspects of social order which are necessarily universal because the nature of a public peace requires that they be shared. Like, you know, restraining or neutralizing people who attack others, steal their property, threaten their persons, and so on. To the extent that order is opposed to anarchy it is universal, but beyond that basic level of course societies differ. Which is the serious problem with holding out any kind of positive universal rights, since rights are all socially defined and different societies will have different definitions and scopes.
However one can break down "rights" as memetically associated clusters of behavior. It is not necessary to define rights to exercise the behaviors that constitute them. If the state is passing a public-order, rational basis for establishing law it has a burden to show that any such regulations serve a reasonable purpose. "Rights" then exist in the null-spaces of the law, or are constructed around what the law does address. Thus "freedom of speech", in the absence of any law criminalizing criticism of the ruling party, or attacks on religion, or public gatherings outside of certain limited circumstances, and so on, can obviously be exercised freely. A "right to equality" can be established from the state prosecuting people who discriminate against others on a host of irrelevant factors. Such rights are of course almost always legally recognized anyway, of course, and whether phrased as a negative ("shall not be infringed upon" ring a bell?) or positive assertions is essentially meaningless rhetoric since the execution of those rights is what matters. But because such rights were established as a result of social conflict in particular historical circumstances and have different meanings between societies modelling a "universal right" is therefore problematic without resorting to more or less a priori justifications that are probably not very convincing to someone who does not share the same social and cultural background. Treating them as behaviors and asserting a rational-means test is thus a way of getting around those kinds of cultural and social differences.
And I am under no imperative to rank and order and judge societies, least of all on the relatively nitpicking differences between liberal democracies. In many case a difference may very well just indicate differing social conditions where a rule that may be superfluous somewhere else is needed in that particular context. Obviously using a rational, public order basis demands attention to the context in which the law is being proposed, as should go without saying for any honest reader. Thus the niggling differences between Canadian and American law with regard to free expression could simply be such a case, or it might be that Canada doesn't really require the restrictions that it imposes, though the difference in outcomes is so minor as to make it not terribly important, either. A system of comparison is much more useful when evaluating gross differences than minor ones like that, especially when the influence of context is all-important. Of course, given the complete lack of nuance demonstrated by yourself throughout this debate, such escaping you should not be a surprise.